He has also argued that practical reason has primacy over theoretical reason.
They must be skilled at balancing care for patients and practical daily administrative tasks.
Practical experience combined with museum studies gives you a great advantage over those who haven't got the practical experience.
Prof Jenny Higham, principal of medical school St George's, University of London, told the BBC's Newsnight: "Medicine is both a very practical discipline and also requires a great deal of clinical and practical experience and hence clinical placement capacity also needs to be increased."
Two observations should be made about this way of understanding practical reason.
Consequently, practical moral skepticism does not imply epistemological moral skepticism.
Knowledge of the first is practical knowledge and knowledge of the second is theoretical.
On traditional Aristotelian approaches, practical wisdom is necessary for the possession of any virtue.
If successful, this Anthropological View would reveal an extremely tight relation between our practical concerns and personal identity.
Since the goal of practical reason is action not knowledge, the truth attained by the intellect must be caused by its conformity to right desire.
In Wolff’s Latin texts, practical philosophy is divided into four main disciplines: universal practical philosophy, natural law, politics, and moral philosophy.
Constructivism’s insight is that practical truths should be explained in terms of the constitutive features of practical reasoning, which the notion of ‘construction’ is supposed to capture.
Their investigations of practical reason generally and of legal reasons in particular typically understand their inquiry as setting the requirements of practical rationality not as an actual theory of behavior.
Practical and epistemic varieties of akrasia nonetheless have in common that they involve a kind of fragmentation or inner conflict; Greco uses this characterization to support the idea that both epistemic and practical akrasia are always irrational.
So if the grounding for our practical concerns requires psychological continuity, but psychological continuity (ordinarily) presupposes biological continuity, then the grounding for our practical concerns (ordinarily) requires biological continuity as well.
Having examined two central parts of Kant’s positive project in theoretical philosophy from the Critique of Pure Reason, transcendental idealism and the transcendental deduction, let us now turn to his practical philosophy in the Critique of Practical Reason.
action | agency: shared | Anscombe, Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret | autonomy: personal | Davidson, Donald | events | feminist philosophy, topics: perspectives on autonomy | free will | incompatibilism: (nondeterministic) theories of free will | intention | practical reason | practical reason: and the structure of actions
The notion of medieval practical reason can be investigated in two ways: 1) in light of the distinction between practical and theoretical sciences in the writings of the medieval university masters in the thirteenth and fourteenth centuries; 2) in comparison to the modern understanding of practical reason as described by Immanuel Kant.
In the Critique of Practical Reason, however, Kant asserts that transcendental freedom acquires a determinate content from pure practical reason, through our immediate awareness of the moral law as normatively binding on our will (as a fact of reason), and that the (practical) objective reality thereby conferred on this idea can then be transferred to the ideas of God and Immortality.
In this portion of the system the world is considered neither as it simply is nor as it simply ought to be; instead, either the practical realm of freedom is viewed from the theoretical perspective of the natural world (in which case one considers the postulates that theoretical reason addresses to practical reason) or else, alternatively, the natural world is viewed from the perspective of practical reason or the moral law (in which case one considers the postulates that practical reason addresses to theoretical reason).
practical
adj all
- guided by practical experience and observation rather than theory
adj all
- concerned with actual use or practice
Example: he is a very practical person
adj all
- being actually such in almost every respect
Example: a practical failure
adj all
- having or put to a practical purpose or use
Example: practical mathematics
On this page, there are 20 sentence examples for practical. They are all from high-quality sources and constantly processed by lengusa's machine learning routines.
Grid-Flow technology
Just use the " " button to fragment sentence examples and start your learning flow.
Example output from one of your searches:
In this portion of the system the world is considered neither as it simply is nor as it simply ought to be instead either the practical realm of freedom is viewed from the theoretical perspective of the natural world in which case one considers the postulates that theoretical reason addresses to practical reason or else alternatively the natural world is viewed from the perspective of practical reason or the moral law in which case one considers the postulates that practical reason addresses to theoretical reason